Highlights:Liliana R. Ladner1, Mark G. Swope2, Phyllis Whitehead3
doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5195/ijms.2023.2046
Volume 11, Number 4: 326-329
Received 05 04 2022; Rev-request 01 06 2023; Rev-request 20 10 2023; Rev-recd 05 06 2023; Rev-recd 22 10 2023; Accepted 24 10 2023
ABSTRACT
Background:Ethics education in medical schools lacks uniformity, yielding uncertainty when providers are faced with ethically complex patients. Without streamlined ethics training, providers are less confident in their ability to provide ethically appropriate care for all patients, particularly for those most ethically vulnerable. This case report seeks to elucidate ethical concerns when treating an ethically complex patient. Subsequently, the need for early ethics education is substantiated.
The Case:A 58-year-old unhoused patient with no known medical history presented to the emergency department (ED) for evaluation of an infected foot wound. Imaging confirmed acute gas gangrene osteomyelitis. The patient refused the recommended below-the-knee amputation (BKA) but was amenable to intravenous antibiotic therapy. He was subsequently determined by psychiatry to lack decisional capacity and met the DSM-5 criteria for schizoaffective psychosis. Subsequently, the patient's brother deferred decision-making to the patient, who he believed should make his own medical decisions. Following an ethics consultation, the brother's decision, and by proxy the patient's, was respected.
Conclusion:In this case, the patient's autonomy was prioritized, despite his high level of ethical vulnerability. Ethically conscious treatment was provided despite the implicit stigmatization of homelessness and psychiatric illness. However, an ethics consultation was necessary for this to occur. Ultimately, this paper should serve as a call to action for standardization and prioritization of ethics education during and beyond medical training.
The 1990 Patient Self-Determination Act, which incorporates patient preference into medical decision-making, has incited a paradigm shift in healthcare from paternalistic to patient-centered. Through this act, patients are empowered to play a role in decisions about their own healthcare, for example by making advance directives while capacitated or deciding how much, if any, treatment they desire. By definition, a capacitated patient can understand their illness and treatment options sufficiently to make decisions that are aligned with their personal values. Today patients often do make their own health decisions, however, their legal next of kin can be called on in the event of incapacitation (e.g. traumatic brain injury, stroke, psychosis) without an advance directive.1
The concept of self-determination empowers patients to make their own health decisions yet often falls short for unrepresented, incapacitated patients. Unrepresented patients, which include elderly, homeless, incarcerated, or mentally disabled patients, both lack advance directives and, “available friends or family to make medical decisions as ‘default’ surrogates”.2 These patients are a highly vulnerable population, necessitating a high level of ethical awareness from their healthcare providers.
This ethical literacy can, and should, be implemented early in medical education. As described by clinical ethicists, the “necessity for the teaching of clinical ethics rests in the immutable fact that any serious medical decision involves two components—a technical decision requiring the application of knowledge of basic and clinical sciences to the patient's present problems, and a moral component demanding that the technically correct decision is also morally defensible”.3 When ethics and medicine collide, healthcare providers should be well-equipped to provide optimal care through robust medical and ethical knowledge.
This case-based discussion will highlight the need for improved ethics education in medical schools to mitigate provider uncertainty, as reflected in the care of an incapacitated, unrepresented patient. We will first discuss how providing autonomy for this patient requires an ethical understanding of medical decisional capacity and stigmatization of both homelessness and psychiatric diagnoses. We will subsequently address how early and streamlined ethics education can empower providers to advocate for patient autonomy. The subsequent case describes the treatment of a homeless, incapacitated, unrepresented patient who presented to our institution refusing treatment for a possible life-threatening illness.
A 58-year-old homeless patient presented to the ED for evaluation of an infected foot wound (Figure 1). The patient's brother endorsed a prior hospitalization, during which the patient received a psychiatric diagnosis that he did not disclose to his family. There was no other known medical history. Imaging demonstrated a heel ulcer associated with bone destruction, indicative of acute gas gangrene osteomyelitis. A psychiatric evaluation determined that this patient lacked decisional capacity and met the DSM-5 criteria for schizoaffective psychosis. The patient adamantly refused the recommended BKA but was amenable to intravenous antibiotic therapy. He stated that he knew people who had bad experiences with amputations in the past and believed that his antibiotics would cure him. The patient's closest living relative, a brother, deferred decision-making to the patient, whom he believed should make his own medical decisions. The ethics consultation team was contacted, and the brother's wishes were respected.
Figure 1Timeline Representing the Patient's Clinical and Ethical Course Prior to and During the Described Hospitalization. Pertinent Details Include the Prior Psychiatric Diagnosis, Presenting Clinical Signs, and Subsequent Ethics Committee Consultation.
In this case, an unrepresented, incapacitated patient was given autonomy in his care in lieu of beneficence, as he inevitably did not receive the most highly recommended medical care, the BKA (Figure 1). The ethical framework underlying this decision will be described, followed by a discussion of the need for streamlined ethics education in medical schools. We will begin with discussing ethical aspects of this patients care (decisional capacity, vulnerability of homelessness, stigmatization of psychiatric illnesses) which will substantiate a subsequent discussion of improved ethics education in medical schools.
The patient described was limited in his decisional capacity, yet consistently stated that he did not want the BKA and insisted on continuing with antibiotic therapy. As with the assumption of innocence in law, medicine deems patients capacitated until proven otherwise, and the responsibility to recognize incapacity falls on any licensed physician. Yet, most physicians fail to recognize incapacity due to a lack of training on the matter or limited knowledge of local guidelines. To determine capacity, a provider should adhere to their institution's legal and ethical standards, while evaluating the patient's ability to do the following.4
Two established models of decisional capacity exist, called “four skills” and “sliding scale”, but emphasis in recent years has shifted towards values-based models which question the concordance of a patient's current and longstanding values.5 In this shifting ethical environment, medical students may lack comprehension of the nuances of capacity assessment.6
This patient presented to the hospital without a home or local family and was accordingly predisposed to experience vulnerability and bias. A 2020 study by Gilmer et al demonstrated that homeless patients report a negative perception of healthcare due to worse health outcomes, less preventative care (43-56% have a primary care provider), and high hospital readmission rates.7 These unfortunate experiences may, in part, be modulated by provider bias against this socially and medically complex patient population. When a provider is aware that a patient is homeless, the patient is more likely to report poor-quality treatment, particularly for mental illness, addiction, and chronic pain.8 This sub-optimal treatment coupled with high readmission rates implies that homeless patients simply do not receive appropriate care or resources to stay out of the hospital. Whether due to provider negligence in creating a feasible discharge plan or patient failure to cooperate in the therapeutic relationship (e.g. via limitations to accessing insurance, prescription medications, transportation, or primary care services), homeless patients are more at risk for neglect of chronic conditions that may land them in the ED soon again for a preventable outcome. This was the case for our patient, who through years of neglected treatment for his diabetes and psychoses, found himself highly ill and vulnerable in the ED yet again. Neglect of this vulnerable population violates beneficence, the principle to do good on behalf of every patient. It is never too early in one's medical training to seek awareness of the vulnerability associated with homelessness.
Another factor increasing this patient's risk for vulnerability is the health system- and physician-level bias associated with psychiatric diagnoses. Notably, patients with ischemic heart disease are less likely to receive guideline-consistent treatment (e.g. coronary artery bypass grafting, beta-blockers) if they also have schizophrenia or a related psychosis.8 Due to associated communication barriers, patients with psychosis may experience a sense of implicit coercion, or the sense that they are being involuntarily compelled to make certain decisions. For example, a patient with dangerous psychoses may be coerced to remain in the hospital against their will. Although for their own safety, the unwilling admission of a psychiatric patient is not without harm. Implicit coercion by definition undermines patient autonomy and denigrates the therapeutic patient-provider relationship, leading to provider moral distress as well as patient dissatisfaction.9 Implicitly coercive and autonomy-limiting treatment of patients with psychoses may illicit failure to cooperate in a therapeutic relationship and worsen their outcomes in the long run.9 If the patient described in this case experienced implicit coercion in a healthcare setting, his perceived lack of autonomy may have encouraged failure to cooperate with prior medical recommendations, increasing his risk for disease progression to this current hospitalization. Patients with psychosis are a highly vulnerable population at risk for implicit coercion, limited autonomy, and subsequent rehospitalization, and awareness of this social stigmatization should be built into medical education.
Successful treatment of patients in socially marginalized groups (e.g. without a home, or with a psychiatric diagnosis) requires a commitment to the ethical principle of patient autonomy. Moreover, inadequate ethics education may inhibit providers from responding quickly and appropriately to ethical dilemmas in patient care. However, strong ethical awareness is not without strong ethics education. Thus, the authors propose standardized and hands-on ethics training among healthcare providers to provide optimal care for similarly incapacitated, unrepresented patients. To achieve this goal, the current state of ethics education requires restructuring.
A 1985 article “Basic Curricular Goals in Medical Ethics,” argued that medical ethics should be a required component of the medical school curriculum, and this notion was added to the Liaison Committee on Medical Education standards the same year.10 Subsequently, medical educators began to incorporate human ethics into their courses, yet the early implementation of ethics education was fraught with inconsistency. Two decades later, in 2002, among syllabi at the 58 responding medical schools, there were ten course objectives, eight teaching methods, 39 content areas, and six assessment methods.11 This non-standardized, lecture-based education model may insufficiently or inconsistently prepare students to develop medical ethics literacy before they enter the clinic.
An optimal ethics curriculum would empower students to step outside of the textbook and think critically. Through a hands-on curriculum that introduces real-world clinical experiences of providers and patients, students can challenge each other and discuss their uncertainty in a non-clinical setting. Subsequently, these students may be more comfortable questioning ethical decision-making as clinicians. More hands-on models have been successfully implemented in several medical schools. For example, the Students' Medical Ethics Rounds (SMER) model of ethics education, where students role-played, had discussions, and conversed with experts, improved confidence in tackling ethical problems in 89.8% of participating students.12 This model provides students with early exposure to ethically complex topics, which will increase their capacity to address ethical uncertainty and ultimately improve patient care. A standardized, clinically applicable ethical training model would equip students to challenge ethical dilemmas as they arise, ultimately improving patient care.
In summary, in this case-based discussion, we outline ethical aspects of treating an incapacitated, unrepresented patient including decisional capacity, the vulnerability of homelessness, and the stigmatization of psychiatric illness. We subsequently address the need for standardized ethics education to appreciate these dilemmas. Without providers committed to a critical awareness of capacity and vulnerability, the patient described may have been subject to an undesired amputation. When highly vulnerable patients require medical care, a strong ethics foundation can improve their provider's understanding of the way forward. By challenging healthcare students early in their careers to be critical of autonomy-limiting decisions, we can better care for a common yet unjustly treated population: the unrepresented, incapacitated patient.
Title: A Case-Based Call to Action for the Standardization of Medical School Ethics Education
Main Problem to Solve: Healthcare providers are inconsistently trained to care for ethically complex patients, for whom there is uncertainty in determining who will or how to make appropriate medical decisions. In ethics curricula at 58 medical schools, there were ten course objectives, eight teaching methods, 39 content areas, and six assessment methods (11).
Aim of Study: To propose a revision of ethics education in medical schools, through analysis of an ethically complex patient's story.
Methodology: A patient's hospital experience is first described, then specific ethical aspects are addressed, followed by a discussion of current and proposed medical school ethics education models.
Results: The patient described does not have the ability to consent for himself, however, he requests a treatment that is not medically recommended. This poses an ethical dilemma for his healthcare team, who decide to respect his wishes after consultation with an ethics committee. Were it not for consultation with the ethics committee, it is unlikely that each provider could address this dilemma with certainty.
Conclusion: Ethics education lacks uniformity. Thus, earlier, more clinically applicable ethics education models are necessary for the early stages of medical training. Moreover, increased provider comfort in addressing ethical uncertainty will promote patient-centered medical care.
The authors acknowledge the patient, the patient's family, and the treating team.
The Authors have no funding, financial relationships or conflicts of interest to disclose.
Conceptualization: LRL, PW. Data Curation: LRL. Investigation: LRL. Supervision: MGS, PW. Visualization: LRL. Writing - Original Draft: LRL, PW. Writing - Review Editing: LRL, MGS, PW.
1. Brown M. Who Would You Choose? Appointing an Agent with a Medical Power of Attorney. J Am Geriatr Soc. 1997;16(4):147–50.
2. Pope T. Unbefriended And Unrepresented: Better Medical Decision Making For Incapacitated Patients Without Healthcare Surrogates. Georgia State University Law Review. 2017;
3. Pellegrino E, Siegler M, Singer P. Teaching clinical ethics. J Clin Ethics. 1990 Fall;1(3):175–80.
4. Appelbaum PS, Grisso T. Assessing Patients' Capacities to Consent to Treatment. N Engl J Med. 1988;319(25):1635–8.
5. Appel JM. A Values-Based Approach to Capacity Assessment. J Leg Med. 2022;42(1–2):53–65.
6. Curlin FA, Lawrence RE, Fredrickson J. An Ethical Façade? Medical Students' Miscomprehensions of Substituted Judgment. Von Elm E, editor. PLoS ONE. 2009;4(2):e4374.
7. Gilmer C, Buccieri K. Homeless Patients Associate Clinician Bias With Suboptimal Care for Mental Illness, Addictions, and Chronic Pain. J Prim Care Community Health. 2020;11:215013272091028.
8. Kisely S, Campbell LA, Wang Y. Treatment of ischaemic heart disease and stroke in individuals with psychosis under universal healthcare. Br J Psychiatry. 2009;195(6):545–50.
9. Fakhoury WKH, White I, Priebe S. Be Good to Your Patient: How the Therapeutic Relationship in the Treatment of Patients Admitted to Assertive Outreach Affects Rehospitalization. J Nerv Ment Dis. 2007;195(9):789–91.
10. Culver CM, Clouser KD, Gert B, Brody H, Fletcher J, Jonsen A, et al. Basic Curricular Goals in Medical Ethics. N Engl J Med. 1985;312(4):253–6.
11. DuBois JM, Burkemper J. Ethics Education in U.S. Medical Schools: A Study of Syllabi. Acad Med. 2002;77(5):432–7.
12. Beigy M, Pishgahi G, Moghaddas F, Maghbouli N, Shirbache K, Asghari F, et al. Students' medical ethics rounds: a combinatorial program for medical ethics education. J Med Ethics Hist Med. 2016;9:3.
Liliana R. Ladner, 1 Third-year Medical Student. Virginia Tech Carilion School of Medicine, Roanoke, VA, USA.
Mark G. Swope, 2 PhD. Department of Medical Ethics, Carilion Roanoke Memorial Hospital, Roanoke, VA, USA.
Phyllis Whitehead, 3 PhD, APRN, ACHPN, PMGT-BC, FCNS, FAAN. Department of Medical Ethics, Carilion Roanoke Memorial Hospital, Roanoke, VA, USA.
About the Author: Liliana Ladner is a third-year medical student at the Virginia Tech Carilion School of Medicine. She is a student member of the Carilion Clinic Ethics Consultation Committee, former President of the Virginia Tech Carilion Humanism in Medicine Club, Chair of the Honor Board, and recipient of the American Academy of Neurology Medical Student Research Scholarship.
Correspondence: Liliana R. Ladner. Address: 2 Riverside Circle, Roanoke VA 24016. Email: lilianaladner@vt.edu
Editor: Francisco J. Bonilla-Escobar; Student Editors: Eugenia M. Ramos-Dávila & Hang-Long (Ron) Li; Copyeditor: Sebastian Diebel; Proofreader: Amy Phelan; Layout Editor: Ana Maria Morales; Process: Peer-reviewed
Cite as Ladner LR, Swope MG, Whitehead P. A Case-Based Discussion Supporting Ethics Education in Medical Schools. Int J Med Stud. 2023 Oct-Dec;11(4):326-9.
Copyright © 2023 Liliana R. Ladner, Mark G. Swope, Phyllis Whitehead
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
International Journal of Medical Students, VOLUME 11, NUMBER 4, November 2023